Role of Intention (Cetaana)
in Buddhist Ethical Doctrine of Kamma
Bhikkhu Thich Nhat-Tu
---o0o---
It is no denying fact that the Buddha for the first time in history of
thought has laid stress on the importance of intention or volition (cetanaa) in
performing an act ethically. Cetanaa "refers only to the self-centred,
goal-directed and result-oriented volitional disposition which impels the
worldly individual (puthujjana)."[1] Ethical good (kusala) or bad
(akusala), merit (pu~n~na) or demerit (paapa) leading to their perspective
ethical consequences will be depended on the level and quality of intention
(cetanaa) of the ethical agent. If the intention of performing an act is
present in high level, the result (vipaka) definitely bears the corresponding
high level. If it is absent, the result is lessened in quality of bearing fruit
or may not bear any fruit. Similarly, if the quality of intention is ethically
good, the acts having good intended intention bear wholesome consequence; while
the acts having evil intended will, bear unwholesome consequence. This
interpretation, however, should not be confused with the statement that the
Buddha’s theory of kamma is of utilitarian type in the sense that it lays
stress on the consequence. It should be noted here that Buddhist ethics can be
considered as cetanaa-utilitarianism, which emphasizes the agent’s intention
(cetanaa) over the consequence of actions performed by him.The famous
definition of kamma attributed to the Buddha is read as: "Cetanaha"m
bhikkhave kamma"m vadaami; cetayitvaa kamma"m karoti kaayena vaacaaya
manasaa,"[2] literally means "Monks, intention or determinate
thought,[3] I say, is kamma. When intention is manifested, one acts by physical
deed, speech or thought."[4] This definition is reflected in the first
twin-verse of the Dhammapada, where it runs: "Mind is the fore-runner of
all mental states [and deeds] (dhammaa). All mental states [and deeds] have
mind as the command chief as well as their maker. If one acts or speaks with an
evil mind, dukkha follows him just as the wheel follows the hoof-print of the
ox that draws the cart . . . Similarly, if one acts or speaks with a good mind,
happiness follows him like a shadow that never leaves him."[5] These two
statements are of the same emphasis that the taming and understanding the mind
or intentional motive is necessary to the ethical agent if moral practice and
mental training are to be cultivated in order to attain higher spirituality or
perfect enlightenment. It is, however, of great controversy in giving
interpretation to the above-mentioned definition. Before proceeding to analysis
of the relation between kamma and cetanaa, it will be worthwhile to look at the
interpretation given by scholars then to turn briefly to a consideration of
their use in the context appeared.
Most of the Pali scholars are inclined to define "kamma as exclusively
cetanaa" (kammaha"m cetana"m vadaami). McDermott, thus, writes:
"In contrast to the Sarvaastivaadin opinion on this point, the P� li schools consider all kamma to be
cetanaa. Mental acts are pure intentional impulse. Acts of body and voice are
intentional impulses which put the body and voice in motion, and not simply the
actions ensuant upon volition."[6] He further points out the common
translation of kamma as cetanaa that, "the Buddhist understanding of kamma
is what usually translated as ‘volition,’ namely cetanaa."[7] Poussin is
perhaps the first thinker, who interprets kamma as exclusively cetanaa:
"Karma is volition and voluntary action,"[8] and "Karma is
twofold: (1) volition (cetanaa), or mental or spiritual action (maanasa), and
(2) what is born from volition, what is done by volition."[9] His
reductive interpretation of kamma into cetanaa is seen clearly when he writes:
"Buddhism, on the contrary, teaches that there is no Karman without
consciousness and even premeditation."[10] In another passage, he does so
when stressing the importance of the concept of cetanaa coined by the Buddha:
"we must consider this definition, ‘Karman is volition, and bodily or
verbal action which follows volition,’ as one of the steps in the history of
the Indian thought."[11] Halbfass is appeared to identify kamma with
cetanaa though he considers correctly the former is primary while the latter secondary
in nature: "a notion of agency which defines the act as rooted in, or even
as essentially identical with, volition and decision (cetanaa) and interprets
its vocal or physical implementation as a secondary phenomenon."[12] The
discussion of Krishan, in this regard, is found precisely similar, "The
Buddha for the first time propounded that moral karma is essentially mental in
its nature."[13] Karunaratna is, in his scholarly article on cetanaa in
the Encyclopaedia of Buddhism,[14] of the view that cetanaa and kamma are
synonymous in denoting the idea of moral action in Buddhism. Thus he writes:
"The all too brief definition states expressly, precisely and concisely
that cetanaa and kamma are equivalent, and therefore, interchangeable as terms
denoting the essential meaning of moral action,"[15] or "Thus,
cetanaa becomes one with kamma creating consequences which serve to feed the
further intensification of the self-centred activity of the will."[16] On
the basis of this equation, he concludes that the path leading to the cessation
of kamma is identical with the path leading to the cessation of cetanaa and
saaakhaaraa.[17] Von Glasenapp, in this regard, strongly claims that ". .
. the Buddha and the other sages have declared that not the action itself, but
exclusively the intention, the conscious willing of the person acting
(cetanaa), are of decisive significance."[18] Unlike Nyanatiloka[19] and
others, Payutto carefully defines kamma as cetanaa-kamma, rather than
exclusively cetanaa, when he writes: "Etymologically speaking, kamma means
‘work’ or ‘action.’ But in the context of Dhamma we define it more specifically
as ‘actions based on intention (cetanaa)’ or ‘deeds willfully done.’ Actions
that are free of intention are not considered to be kamma in the Buddha’s
teaching."[20] In his well-known book, the Buddha and His Teaching, Narada
has already stated this interpretation earlier:(1) The Paali term kamma,
literally means action or doing. Any kind of intentional action whether mental,
verbal or physical is regarded as kamma. It covers all that is included in the
phrase, ‘though, word and deed.’ Generally speaking, all good and bad actions
constitute kamma. (2) In its ultimate sense, kamma means all moral and immoral
volition. Involuntary, unintentional or unconscious actions, though technically
deed, do not constitute kamma, because volition, the most important factor in
determining kamma, is absent.[21]While partially agreeing with the first part
of his definition, that kamma is any intentional action whether mental, verbal
or physical, I do not think the second part of his definition is tenable. For
him, any action without intention does not bear its fruit. Such an
interpretation proves somewhat unsatisfactory in analysis of kamma as mere
cetanaa. The reduction of kamma into exclusive cetanaa can not be accepted
because the Buddha does not deny the existence of unintentional actions
(acetanaa-kammaa) rather than he stresses the important role of cetanaa in
directing and determining human ethical actions. Moreover, it should be noted
here that "not only the intentional stimulus, but the action itself is
also significant from the Buddhist point of view."[22]
Thus, the interpretation of kamma as mere cetanaa by modern scholars is
unsatisfactory. This interpretation is in fact rooted from the commentary
literature, especially in the Visuddhimagga and the Dhammasa"nga.nii
A.t.thakathaa of the great Pali commentator, Buddhaghosa. It is relevant here
to take note on his analysis on the Buddha’s statement. Quoting the Buddha
(Cetanaaha"m bhikkhave kamma"m vadaami), Buddhaghosa identifies kamma
as exclusively cetanaa.[23] He inserts that "kamma means consciousness or
intention of the good and the bad, merit and demerit."[24] This finds
support in the Atthasaalinii, where kamma is defined as cetanaa and the mental
states associated with it.[25] He however comes very close to the point, when
he claims intention is the source of physical deed, verbal deed and mental deed
. . . mind is the door of mental action."[26] In this direction, it is
believed that Harivarman’s interpretation of the same is more relevant to the
statement of the Buddha, and therefore agreeable. For instance, in his
Satyasiddhi'saastra,[27] he appears to claim that kamma is not only cetanaa but
the action manifested from it as well. This logically follows that action
manifested from intention would include physical, verbal and mental deeds, and
those actions unassociated with or not originated from intention including
unintentionally physical, verbal and mental deeds. On the same page, he
stresses the importance of the mind, when he writes, "ethical qualities,
good and evil, are controlled by the agent’s mind,"[28] or "without
the presence of the mind, ethical good and evil is impossible."[29] He
points further out that "actions whether ethical good or bad depends on
the state of the mind."[30] He sees that unintentional action certainly
produces its fruition, though it is ethically lessened, when he stresses that
"the non-intentional kamma is not great sin."[31] This gets support
from scriptural passage, where it is stated "he [Naa.taputta] acted
unintentionally (asa~ncetanikam) and hence it is not a great sin or
crime."[32]Amongst the modern scholars, Poussin, as I believe, rightly
points out that the Buddhist definition of kamma as ‘intention together with
the action,’ which follows upon it, to be one of the steps in the history of
Indian thought.[33] The emphasis in Buddhist theory of kamma on goal-oriented
intentional motive behind the action is to bring out the forceful importance of
ethical orientation, and this in turn gives rise to deed-direction and
tendencies, which affect or determine the future states and conditions of the
ethical agent. What should be noted here is that by declaring "cetanaaha"m
bhikkhave kamma"m vadaami," the Buddha fundamentally lays great
stress on the importance of intention (cetanaa) behind the action as a major
factor in producing an ethical act leading to moral consequence, good or bad.
Having stressed the decisiveness of intention in determining the tendency and
the fruition of an act, the Buddha does not, in this context, deny the
existence of the other three kinds of kamma, namely unintentional acts of body
(acetanaa-kaaya-kamma), unintentional acts of speech (acetanaa-vacii-kamma),
and unintentional acts of mind (acetanaa-mano-kamma). Because from three main
modes of kamma, viz., bodily act, verbal act and mental act, we can divide them
into two sub-modes of actions, namely intentional actions and unintentional
actions. Of the first group, there are intentional bodily action, intentional
verbal action and intentional mental action, which bears greatly ethical
result, good or bad. Belonging to the second, there are unintentional bodily
action, unintentional verbal action and unintentional mental action, which bear
lessened or minimized ethical result. The Buddha does not reduce all kammas to
cetanaa-kamma, as the scholars did. The emphasis on the role of cetanaa no
doubt is the Buddha’s contribution to not only the theory of kamma but also to
the ethical tendencies as well its understanding leading to the specific
ethical effects. Ch’en states that the stress on cetanaa was a significant
point added by the Buddha to the prevailing views concerning karma.[34]
McDermott impressively writes, "What is unique with Gotama and his
followers is the importance which he places on the role of intention. Only in
Buddhism could the intentional impulse (cetanaa) be defined as
kamma."[35]It is here of significance to observe that the Buddha’s
statement "cetanaaha"m bhikkhave kamma"m vadaami" does not
amount to the statement that "kamma is exclusively cetanaa"
(kammaha"m cetanaa"m vadaami), because kamma is of ‘twofold category’
to which cetanaa or cetanaa-kamma as a variety of this twofold category
belongs, and the other being acetanaa-kamma. The logical distinction between
the subject, kamma, and the predicate, cetanaa, should not confuse the reader
that they are mutually ‘identical.’ Employing the term ‘analytic statement and
synthetic statement’ coined by Kant, we can accordingly put the Buddha’s
statement in this way: (1) cetanaa is kamma; this is of the form of analytic
proposition, like that of ‘'Si"m'sapaa is a tree’. Here cetanaa is a
variety of kamma, and (2) kamma is purely cetanaa; it has the form of synthetic
proposition, like that of ‘This tree is a 'Si"m'sapaa.’ Here the Buddha’s
analytic statement "cetanaa is kamma" does not amount to the
synthetic statement as misinterpreted by scholars that "kamma is exclusively
cetanaa." In the context of the Buddha’s statement, the analytic
proposition is meant that the subject cetanaa is contained in the predicate
kamma. This statement does not discuss something new instead of repeating that
cetanaa is a kind, the most important kind, of kamma. The repetition here,
however, makes significance that is more ethical to agent’s will in performance
of any action.Furthermore, given the logically faultless inference form ‘a=b’
to ‘b=a’ we cannot proceed from the statement, ‘cetanaa is kamma’ to the
statement ‘kamma is exclusively cetanaa,’ for the first is logically true while
the second false. This wrong identification is sound similar to the statement
‘everything is identical with something’ mistakenly identified with ‘something
is identical with everything,’ for the concept ‘everything’ is a greater
category whereas the concept ‘something’ smaller, which should be contained in
the former instead of being identified with the former. The same holds true
with kamma and cetanaa.Moreover, one should pay attention not only to the first
part of the Buddha’s statement "cetanaaha"m bhikkhave kamma"m
vadaami," but also to the second part of the statement following the first
"cetayitvaa kamma"m karoti kaayena vaacaaya manasaa,"[36] which
makes the context more ethical clearly. Here the Buddha does confirm not only
that intention (cetanaa) is a special kind of kamma in moral judgment, tendency
and ethical performance, but also link it with the bodily action (kaayakamma),
verbal action (vaciikamma), and mental action (manokamma) to make significantly
the role of intention. According to the most popular threefold classification
of kamma[37] made by the Buddha into acts of body (kaayakamma), acts of speech
(vaciikamma), and acts of mind (manokamma), each of these acts produces
consequences: "All kamma whether good or evil bears consequence. There is
no kamma, no matter how small, which is void of consequence."[38] However,
among these three kinds of kamma, mental kind is the most important, as it is
stated in the following passage: "Listen, of these three kamma classified
by me, I say that mental kamma (manokamma) has the heaviest consequences for
the committing of evil deeds, for the existence of evil deeds, not action s of
the body or speech."[39] It is clear that, according to McFarlane,
"the emphasis on the psychology of intentions in traditional ethical
teaching and spiritual practice should not lead to the undermining of physical
behaviour and actual consequences." He further explains that "It would
be incorrect to say that the intention or will to perform an unwholesome act,
which was not actually carried out, would produce the same effect as the actual
performance of such an act."[40]In reality, there are actions, which are
not sprung from intention or devoid of motive proved, harmful or beneficial to
the ethical agent as well as to others. Both the doer and the recipient are to
experience its fruition, more or less suffered or pleasant through unwitting
actions performed. Take an example the case of being shot death by mistake. The
deceased, who has no intention or willing to be died, is certainly suffered as
a result of wrong identification or mistake by unintentional agent. The
unintentional shooter without motive of killing anyone is responsible for his
carelessly ethical action, say wrong shooting, being produced in the court and
then to be put in prison. Because of being in the prison, he may loose his job
or stopped his habitual work unwittingly. An encounter example can be seen in
the case of a person who keeps away scraps of food without any intention to
give it to anyone.[41] But then a hungry dog comes by and has a delicious meal
out of it. His scraps of food were helpful and beneficial to the life of the
dog. When the time to come for that unintentionally helpful kamma to mature, he
will enjoy its fruit, even ethically lessened comparatively to that of
intention feeding the dog, say being helped by someone incidentally, as it has
been happened in the real.
This idea would be clear with the help of the following analysis. Actual
murder with evil intention no doubt has greater effect; with no evil intention
still has effect, though ethically minor; and even the mere thought of murder
unaccompanied by any performance is ethically wrong, from the Buddhist standpoint.
That is to say, mental action unaccompanied with outward performance and that
the performance of the physical deeds, either accompanied with intention or
not, is considered to produce specific kammic effects, at least on two
respects, namely on the planning-doer himself and on the recipient. So far as
the part of the ethical agent is concerned, even the ‘mere’ intention, whether
wholesome or unwholesome, will give some effect, say disturbing the
peacefulness of the mind of the planning-doer, who plans to make his intention
possible. With respect to the recipient, let us say for instance, the
destructive intention may either give rise to the feeling of being disturbed by
intentional violence of the planning-doer, or even he is facing death due to being
killed unintentionally by the evil-doer, respectively. In the Buddha’s
statement, there is obviously intention (cetanaa). On the other hand, there is
crucially also ‘what is born from intention,’ namely bodily action
(kaayakamma), vocal action (vaciikamma) and mental action (manokamma). If kamma
were merely cetanaa there should be no other actions named bodily action
(kaayakamma), vocal action (vaciikamma) and mental action (manokamma).[42] In
fact, these actions obviously exist. The reducing identification of kamma as
exclusive cetanaa is, therefore, untenable.In the teachings of the Buddha, the
relationship between the levels of intention and performance of that intention
should be suitably acknowledged. As the motive force or guiding manager,
intention is conductive to performing an act after having conscious choice of
objects of preference by the nature of an awareness-mind. Where there is
intention, there may be tendency to make it possible. Similarly, where there is
an increase of intensity of mental activity or intention to an unbearable
level, the tendency of performance of something would be transformed into
external activities, namely, either bodily action (kaayakamma), vocal action
(vaciikamma) or mental action (manokamma). In other words, not every intention
will lead to the actual performance. Depending on the levels of intentional
motive, some dynamically become physical or verbal activities while some
remains mental activities only. In the case of being mental activities, the
effect of the intention on both the planing-doer and the recipient is ethically
lessened or minimized,[43] whereas with regard to intention having transformed
into outward performance, the effect is ethically serious. Take the ‘initial
thought of destroying life’ and the ‘ actual act of destroying life’ as an
example. The intentional thought, ‘I want to kill A’ is unwholesome thought in
nature. This may produce some unfortunate result, if the intentional doer is
not remorseful or till in hoping so doing. In the case of someone wishing to
kill A with the plan of murder, the effect of being unfortunate here and
hereafter is more serious. If the murder is actually happened after having
evilly willed with careful planning and acting, the effect becomes most serious
comparatively with the first two cases.Thus, in the Buddha’s teaching generally
and in the context of the Buddha’s statement particularly, kamma can not be
exclusively identified with cetanaa because if it were so, the effect of
‘wishing to perform something’ and the ‘actual performance of that something’
is one and the same thing.[44] Then there should be no enlightenment at all
because no one is absolutely pure and perfect in his intention-history; or one
may have at least once thought of unwholesome deed.[45] Similarly, there should
be no need of moral practice and spiritual training for enlightenment, for the
mere wishing of becoming enlightened would be enough to make it possible.[46]
These statements are found irrational, just because ‘intentional thought of
doing something unwholesome’ is exclusively mistakenly identified with the ‘sin
of performance that act,’ and in the same manner, ‘wishing to be enlightened’
with ‘enlightenment’ or moral practice and mental development for attaining
that enlightenment, respectively.In the Nikaaya, we do find passages supporting
the idea that not only intention is responsible for determining kamma-vipaaka,
the action, physical or vocal, as well: "If one does not think (ceteti),
nor arrange (pakappeti), but dwell on (anuseti) [something], this become a
cause for the persistence of consciousness . . . [And] in the future birth and
death, sorrow, lamentation, suffering, grief and tribulation arise."[47]
This is so because, one is responsible for his ignorance,[48] as McDermott
comments "although a misdeed done in ignorance is not as serious in its
effects as a deed done intentionally, it is nonetheless not without efforts of
its own, for man is culpable for his continued ignorance."[49]Notes
[1] EB. IV. s.v. cetanaa: 86b.
[2] A. III, 415.
[3] This render is first used by E.M. Hare in his GS. III. 294.
[4] Here quoted are different translations made by scholars. Payutto
translates this as "Bhikkhu! Intention, I say, is kamma. Having willed, we
create kamma through body, speech and mind." Payutto (1993): 6. Narada
renders it as "I declare, O Bhikkhus, that volition (cetanaa) is kamma.
Having willed one acts by body, speech and thought." (196). McDermott also
renders it similarly "I say, monks, that cetanaa is kamma; having intended
(cetayitvaa), one does a deed by body, word or thought." (1984: 26).
McFarlane renders cetanaa as choice translating the sentence as "It is
choice or intention that I call karma mental work
for having chosen, a man acts by body, speech and mind." (1994: 27).
[5] Manopubba"ngamaa dhammaa/ manose.t.thaa manomayaa/ manasaa ce
padu.t.thena/ bhaasati vaa karoti vaa/ tato na"m dukkhamanveti/
cakka"mva vahato pada"m. (Dhp. 1). Translation is adopted with
modification from Tin (1990): 1-2.
[6] McDermott (1984): 12-3. For argument on this point, see Poussin (1927):
124-5.
[7] McDermott (1984): 26.
[8] Poussin (1982): 57. This book was first published in 1917.
[9] Poussin (1982): 68.
[10] Poussin (1982): 67.
[11] Poussin (1982): 70.
[12] Halbfass (1998): 214-5.
[13] Krishan (1997): 62, 209.
[14] EB. IV. s.v. cetanaa: 86-97.
[15] EB. IV. s.v. cetanaa: 89a.
[16] EB. IV. s.v. cetanaa: 91a.
[17] EB. IV. s.v. cetanaa: 92b.
[18] Von Glasenapp (1963): 29. Emphasis added.
[19] BD. s.v karma: 91-4.
[20] Payutto (1993): 6.
[21] Narada (1973): 195. Numbering added.
[22] McDermott (1984): 28.
[23] DhsA. 88.
[24] kamma naama kusalaakusalacetanaa. Visuddhimagga, p. 614. This sentence
literally means kamma is the name of moral and immoral intention or
consciousness.
[25] Asl. p. 88.
[26] cetanaa kaayakamma"m naama . . . cetanaa vaacikamma naama . . .
cetanaa manokamma"m . . .citta"m manokammadvaaram naama, p. 96.
[27] Satyasiddhi'saastra 3. 100.
[28] pu.nya"m paapa"m sarva"m cittaadhaaniiam.[29] na
cittavyatirikta"m pu.nyam paapam astiiti.[30] karma.na"m cittabalaat
pu.nya paapa vibhaaga.h.[31] asa~ncentanika"m karma na mahaasaavadyam.
Satyasiddhi'saastra. 2. 84.
[32] Quoted in Krishan (1997): 64.
[33] Quoted from McDermott (1984): 29. Emphasis added.
[34] Ch’en (1968): 32f.[35] McDermott (1984): 29.
[36] A. III, 415.
[37] See, for example, this division at A. III. 415; M. I. 206.
[38] J. IV. 390.
[39] M. I. 373.
[40] McFarlane (1994): 27.
[41] This is adopted from Indasara (1988): 18-9. I however disagree with him
when he contradictorily says that the mistake in the example is only a kind of
‘kattaka-kamma’ bearing no fruit.[42] Mental action (manokamma) is identified
with cetanaa in some specific context. See, for example, the sentence
"manasaa ce padu.t.thena" of twin-verse 1-2 of the Dhammapada. Cf.
Tin (1990): 1 n.2.
[43] This is different from the spiritual state of enlightenment of an
Arahat or the Buddha.
[44] Karunaratna is however of diverse point of view, when he give an
interpretation on the passage of Budhaghosa as quoted below: "for instance
the mere harboring of criminal intent to kill amounts to kamma, and that by
ill-will, not by actual life-taking" (Manodvaare pana cadhakacetanaaya
uppannamattaaya eva kammapathabhedo hoti, so va kho vyaapaadavasena na
paa.naatipaatavasena. Asl., p. 90). Here he does not differentiate the mental
act ‘ill-will’ with the bodily action manifested from ill-will, namely killing,
in terms of life-taking. These two acts, in fact, can not be considered
identical equally ethical wrong, and therefore their level of criminal can not
be identified as the same. EB. IV. 94b.[45] This argument is derived from the
passage where the Buddha criticizes past-action determination
(pubbekatahetuvaada) along with theistic determination
(issaranimmaanahetuvaada) and accidentalism (ahetu-apaccayavaada) as immoral
theories. A. I. 137; M. II. 214-222; Cf. Vbh. 367.
[46] This argument is derived from the passage where the Buddha addresses to
the householders who want to gain longevity, status, happiness, rank and
rebirth in heaven must observe the practice leading to the same. A mere wish or
prayer will not work. A. III. 47.
[47] S. II. 65. Translation quoted in McDermott (1984): 28.
[48] Dhp. 1-2, 161.
[49] McDermott (1984): 28.
References(The references to the Pali texts and their translations are to
the Pali text society standard edition.)
Ch’en, Kenneth K.S. (1968) Buddhism: the Light of Asia. New York: Barron’s
Educational Series.Halbfass, Wilhelm. (1992). Tradition and Reflection:
Explorations in Indian Thought. Delhi: Sri Satguru Publications.
Indasara,Wasin (1988a) Theravada Buddhist Principles, vol. I. Bangkok: Mah� makut Buddhist University.
Indasara,Wasin (1988b) Theravada Buddhist Principles, vol. II. Bangkok: Mah� makut Buddhist University.
Krishan, Yuvraj. (1997). The Doctrine of Karma. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
McDermott, James Paul. (1984) Development in the Early Buddhist Concept of
Kamma/Karma. Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal.
McFarlane, Stewart (1994) "Buddhism" in Jean Holm & John
Bowker (ed.) Making Moral Decisions. London: Pinter Publishers.
Narada, Mahathera. (1973) The Buddha and His Teaching. Singapore: Singapore Buddhist
Meditation Center.
Payutto, Bhikkhu P. A. (1993) Good, Evil and Beyond Kamma in the Buddha’s
Teaching. Bangkok:
Buddhadhamma Foundation.Poussin, L. de la Vallee. (1927) La Morale Bouddhique.
Paris: Nouvelle
Librairie Nationale.
Poussin, L. de la Vallee. (1982). The Way to Nirv� a. Delhi:
Sri Satguru Publications, 1st ed. 1917.
Tin, Daw Mya. (tr.) (1990). The Dhammpada: Verses and Stories. Sarnath:
Central Institute of Higher Tibetan Studies, 1st Ed. 1985.
Von Glasenapp, Helmuth. (1963) Immortality and Salvation in Indian Religions
tr. E.F.J. Payne. Calcutta:
Susil Gupta India Ltd, Indian reprint.
Source :
www.buddhismtoday.com